You are told that the
(fi ctitious) Ancient Book Act 2009 has
just received the Royal Assent and that s. 1 provides, ‘It shall be an offence
to destroy any book printed before 1800’. Discuss the criminal liability of
each party (in relation to the 2009 Act) in the following situation.
Arthur owns 200
books, which he thinks are worthless. He is concerned in case any of the books
were printed before 1800 and consults Ben, an expert on old books, who assures
him that all the books were printed long after 1800. Arthur destroys the books
and is now horrifi ed to discover that
three of them were printed in 1750.The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens
rea
Answer plan
• Strict
liability—Sweet v Parsley [1969]
• Presumption of mens
rea—B v DPP [2000]
• The exceptions
• Recklessness
• Mistake—Morgan
[1976]
• Ben’s liability
under the Serious Crime Act 2007
Suggested answer
The first point to
note is that s. 1 of the Ancient Book Act 2009 is silent as to the mens rea
requirement of the offence. This could mean that the offence is one of absolute
liability (i.e., strict liability in the sense that no mens rea whatsoever is
required). Alternatively it could be a strict liability offence in the sense
that intention, recklessness or negligence is only required as regards one or
more elements of the actus reus. The imposition of absolute liability may be
very harsh on the defendant. For example, in Pharmaceutical Society of Great
Britain v Storkwain [1986] 2 All ER 635, the House of Lords upheld the
conviction of a pharmacist who had given drugs to a patient with a forged
doctor’s prescription, although the court found the pharmacist blameless.
Whilst the decision demonstrates the inherent unfairness of strict liability,
it can be justifi ed on the basis that the
misuse of drugs is a grave social evil and therefore should be prevented at all
costs.
The first case of
statutory strict liability was R v Woodrow (1846) 15 M & W 404, where the
accused was found guilty of being in possession of adulterated tobacco, even though
he did not know that it was adulterated. Many early decisions revealed an in-consistent
approach as the courts were trying to interpret old statutes in ascertaining the
will of Parliament. However, Lord Reid in the House of Lords’ decision in Sweet
v Parsley [1969] 1 All ER 347 laid down the following guidelines:
(a) Wherever a
section is silent as to mens rea there is a presumption that, in order to give
effect to the will of Parliament, words importing mens rea must be read into
the provision.
(b) It is a universal
principle that if a penal provision is reasonably capable of two
interpretations, that interpretation which is most favourable to the accused
must be adopted.
(c) The fact that
other sections of the Act expressly require mens rea is not in itself sufficient
to justify a decision that a section which is silent as to mens rea creates an
absolute offence. It is necessary to go outside the Act and examine all relevant
circumstances in order to establish that this must have been the intention of
Parliament.
The elements of a crime:
actus reus and mens rea So in Cundy v Le Coq (1884) 13 QB 207, a publican was
found guilty of selling intoxicating liquor to a drunken person under s. 13 of
the Licensing Act 1872, even though the publican did not know and had no reason
to know that the customer was drunk; whereas in Sherras v De Rutzen [1895] 1 QB
918, a publican was not guilty under s. 16(2) of the Licensing Act 1872 of serving
alcohol to a police constable while on duty when the accused did not know or
have reason to know that the police constable was on duty. The former case was
held to be an offence of strict liability, whereas in the latter, in order to
obtain a conviction, the prosecution had to prove mens rea on behalf of the
publican, which they were unable to do.Despite the fact that there is a
presumption in favour of mens rea when a statute is silent, the courts have
been prepared to rebut this presumption on many occasions. The leading case on
this point is Gammon v Attorney-General for Hong Kong [1985] AC 1, where Lord
Scarman set out the applicable principles. If the offence is truly criminal in
character the presumption is particularly strong, but it can be displaced where
the statute is concerned with an issue of social concern. Thus, in Gammon, as
the accused’s activities involved public safety, the Privy Council were
prepared to hold that the legis-lature intended the offence to be one of strict
liability.
On analysis these
principles appear inconsistent. It could be argued that all crimes by definition
are grave social evils, yet if the offence is truly criminal in character,
strict liability does not apply. In practice, the courts have adopted a flexible
approach, but it is recognized that certain spheres of activity are always
likely to attract the conclusion that this is an offence of strict liability.
Thus inflation (R v St Margaret’s Trust Ltd [1958] 2 All ER 289), pollution
(Alphacell Ltd v Woodward [1972] 2 All ER 475), and dangerous drugs
(Pharmaceutical Society of Great Britain v Storkwain, above) are traditional areas
where strict liability has been imposed. However, it does seem in recent years that
the category of grave social concern is expanding to encompass new social
activity to include acting as a director whilst disqualifi ed (R v Brockley [1994] Crim LR 671) and unauthorized
possession of a dangerous dog (R v Bezzina [1994] 1 WLR 1057). However, the
House of Lords have again emphasized the need for the prosecution to prove mens
rea in B (A minor) v DPP [2000] 1 All ER 833, where Lord Hutton stated (at p.
855), ‘the test is not whether it is a reasonable implication that the statute rules
outmens rea as a constituent part of the crime—the test is whether it is a
necessary implication’. Further in R v Lambert [2001] 3 All ER 577, the House
held that although s. 28 of the Misuse of Drugs Act 1971 required the defence
to prove a defence, this only meant introduce evidence of, rather than
establish a defence on the balance of probabilities.
In view of these
developments, it is submitted that it would be most unlikely for s. 1 of the
Ancient Book Act 2009 to be an offence of strict liability, and therefore
Arthur will only be guilty if the prosecution can establish that he had the
necessary mens rea. As Rix LJ observed in R v M [2009] EWCA 2615, even if the
provision in question is silent as to mens rea and other provisions in the
statute expressly require it, the presumption in The elements of a crime: actus
reus and mens rea favour of mens rea will not be rebutted unless the
circumstances are such as to compel such a conclusion. If the court were to
decide that the offence required the prosecution to prove intention, it is
submitted that Arthur would not be convicted. He obtained the opinion of Ben,
an expert and clearly did not desire or even foresee the consequence that
protected books would be destroyed. Arthur has made a mistake, and even if an
accused makes an unreasonable mistake, in accordance with the House of Lords’
decision in DPP v Morgan [1976] AC 182, he is, in the absence of any clear
statutory intent to the contrary, entitled to be judged on the facts as he
believed them to be. If the court decides that the offence could be committed
recklessly, it would still be very difficult for the prosecution to establish
the appropriate mens rea. It is almost certainly the case that subjective
recklessness would have to be proved—i.e., the prosecution must show that the
accused foresaw the consequence and took an unjustified risk (R v Cunningham
[1957] 2 All ER 412 and R v G [2003] 4 All ER 765) (although technically the
latter only deals with the issue of recklessness in relation to criminal damage).
As Arthur sought the opinion of an expert it is diffi cult to see how it could
be argued that he was consciously taking an unjustified risk. It is therefore
submitted that Arthur could be guilty of the offence only if the court decides
that s. 1 of the Ancient Book Act 2009 creates an offence of strict liability.
Turning to Ben’s
liability, if he genuinely believed the books to be of post-1800 vintage and
the courts interpret the offence as requiring at least recklessness on this
issue, he could not be convicted as an accomplice as he would lack the
necessary mens rea. If the offence were held to be one of strict or absolute
liability Ben could only be convicted as an accomplice if he knew of the facts
that constituted the offence—i.e. he knew the books dated from before 1800—see
Johnson v Youden [1950] 1 KB 544.
Alternatively, if Ben
knew or believed the books to date from before 1800 he could be charged with
either:
(i) Doing an act
capable of encouraging or assisting the commission of an offence intending to
encourage or assist its commission contrary to s. 44 of the Serious
Crime Act 2007; or
(ii) Doing an act
capable of encouraging or assisting the commission of an offence believing that
the offence will be committed and that his act will encourage or assist its
commission contrary to s. 45 of the Serious Crime Act 2007.
The act in question
would be giving advice to Arthur he knew to be wrong. The fact that Arthur, in
destroying the books, might have acted without mens rea will not absolve Ben.
If the offence under the Ancient Book Act 2009 is construed as requiring fault
it will be suffi cient for the
prosecution to prove that Ben’s state of mind was such that, had he destroyed
the books, he would have acted with the degree of fault required for the full
offence; see s. 47(5)(a)(iii) of the 2007 Act. If the 2009 Act is a strict
liability offence, Ben can be convicted under the Serious Crime Act 2007,
provided he believed that the books dated from before 1800 or was reckless as
to whether or not they did.
Question 4
Gloria, Wood’s
eccentric aunt, aged 57, was invited to stay with Wood and his girlfriend Mary at
their property on the coast. It was agreed that Gloria would stay for three
weeks and would occupy ‘the lodge’ in the garden of the Wood’s house some 30 yards
away. Gloria also agreed to pay £40 to cover the electricity she would use in
the lodge. Everything went well for two weeks, with all three sharing meals at
the house. However, a change of mood then came over Gloria who decided that she
no longer wanted to have meals with Wood and Mary. Gloria spent more and more
time by herself at the lodge. After 20 days of the holiday Gloria, whose
physical condition had visibly deteriorated, announced that she refused to
leave the lodge and was going to stay there the rest of the winter. This so
enraged Wood and Mary that the next day they told her to leave immediately, which
she did. Six hours later, at 11 pm, Gloria rang their bell pleading to be let
in as she was cold and hungry and had nowhere else to go. Wood and Mary
refused, and during that night Gloria was taken to hospital suffering from
hypothermia. While in hospital, Gloria fell unconscious and was placed on a life
support machine. After five days she was correctly diagnosed by Dr Spock as
being in a persistent vegetative state with no hope of recovery. He accordingly
disconnected the machine. Discuss the criminal responsibility (if any) of Wood
and Mary.The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Answer plan
• Is there a
causative omission?
• Examine the bases
for liability for failing to act—statutory, contractual, and common law
• Distinguish R v
Instan and R v Stone & Dobinson
• Consider R v Miller
and R v Evans
• Consider killing by
gross negligence
• Can a duty of care
be established?
• Is the degree of
fault required made out on the facts?
Suggested answer
The first issue to be
resolved is whether or not Wood and Mary can be said to have caused the death
of Gloria. As there is no positive act by either of them that causes death, the
court would need to investigate whether or not liability can be based on the
failure of either or both of them to prevent Gloria’s death. The question as to
whether an omission, as opposed to an act, can actually cause a consequence is
a moot point. Traditionally, the criminal law has always drawn a clear
distinction between acts and omissions, being loath to punish the latter. Other European countries—e.g., Greece, France and
Germany—do not exhibit the same reluctance, and there is dispute as to whether
the English approach is correct. See in particular the different views of
Professors A. Ashworth (1989) 105 LQR 424 and G. Williams (1991) 107 LQR 109.
However, apart from the numerous statutes that impose a duty to act, e.g., s.
170 of the Road Traffi c Act 1988, it
appears that the common law will impose a duty to act only in very limited
circumstances. There can be no criminal liability imposed on Wood and Mary in
respect of their failing to care for Gloria unless the prosecution can
establish that they were under a positive legal duty to care for her. Such a
duty can be imposed by statute, but that is clearly not the case here.
Similarly a legal duty to act can arise from a contract between the parties. For
example in R v Pittwood (1902) 19 TLR 37, where the defendant, a railway gate operator,
was found guilty of manslaughter when a person was killed crossing a railway line
as a result of the defendant leaving the gate open when a train was coming. In
the present case it could be argued that there was a contractual relationship,
in that Gloria agreed to pay for her electricity and was in occupation of the
lodge, but it is hard to see how any positive duty to care for Gloria can be
implied—and in any event it would be argued that the contract was only for the
initial three-week period, and that it was a purely domestic arrangement not
intended to give rise to legally enforceable obligations.
In respect of Wood it
could be argued that he was under a common law duty to care for Gloria because
she was a relative. Where the relationship is that of parent and child the
common law has had little diffi culty in
identifying a positive legal duty of care so The elements of a crime: actus
reus and mens rea that failing to act can result in liability where it causes
harm; see R v Gibbins and Proctor (1918) 13 Cr App R 134. In R v Instan [1893]
1 QB 450, liability for manslaughter was imposed upon a niece who failed to
care for her aunt with whom she was living, having been given money by the aunt
to supply groceries. Liability in Instant was largely based on the existence of
a blood relationship between the parties. This would seem to suggest that, at
least in the case of Wood, there might be a common law duty to act. It is submitted
that the present case can be distinguished from Instan. In Instan the defend-ant
actually occupied the same house as the deceased, and had expressly undertaken
the task of purchasing food for her, which she subsequently failed to do,
knowing well that her aunt could not fend for herself. In the present case Gloria
decided for herself that she wanted to stay in the lodge alone, thus raising the
question of whether Wood was obliged to do anything more for her than he had
been doing during the fi rst two weeks of
her stay. Furthermore the evidence suggests that it was refusing to readmit
Gloria after she had been told to leave that led to her death—raising the
question of whether
Wood was under any
obligation to readmit Gloria. The much more promising argument for the
prosecution is that a positive legal duty to act at common law arose in respect
of both Wood and Mary because they had allowed a relationship of reliance to
develop between themselves and Gloria. The key authority here is R v Stone and
Dobinson [1977] QB 354. In that case the Court of Appeal upheld convictions for
killing by gross negligence on the basis that the defendants had admitted the
deceased to their house and had attempted to care for her. They then failed to
discharge their duty adequately and failed to summon any assistance in discharging
that duty. The court stressed that the duty to act arose not simply because of
a blood relationship between one of the defendants and the deceased, but
because of the reliance relationship. It could be argued that in allowing
Gloria to stay Wood and Mary allowed a relationship of reliance to develop—but
the present case can be distinguished from Stone and Dobinson on the grounds that
Wood and Mary placed a time limit on Gloria’s stay, and Gloria left of her own
volition. Thus the argument as to whether or not there is any liability for
failing to act is finely balanced. The prosecution could run an alternative
argument on the basis that when Gloria begs to be readmitted to the house Wood
and Mary are aware that their expulsion of Gloria has created a dangerous
situation. There is evidence that Gloria’s physical condition had visibly
deteriorated. Gloria was cold, hungry, and had nowhere to go. There was evidence
that Gloria was eccentric. Applying R v Miller [1983] 1 All ER 978, where the
House of
Lords upheld the
accused’s conviction for criminal damage where he had inadvertently started a
fi re and then, when he realized what he
had done, simply left the building without making any attempt to prevent the
fi re spreading or to call the fi re brigade, it could be argued that by
failing to offer Gloria shelter, Wood and Mary committed culpable omission that
caused Gloria’s death. For the Miller principle to apply, the prosecution would
have to show that the defendants were both aware that their expulsion of Gloria
had created a dangerous situation. On the facts this should not be too
difficult. The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Assuming that the
failure to care for Gloria, or the refusal to readmit her to the house, can
form the basis of liability, the prosecution will have to show that this
omission caused Gloria’s death. It is not necessary for the prosecution to prove
that the omission was the sole or main cause merely that it contributed significantly
to the victim’s death (R v Cheshire [1991] 3 All ER 670). The accused could
argue that the doctor’s turning off the life support system constituted anovus
actus interventions, breaking the chain of causation; but this argument was
rejected by the House of Lords in R v Malcherek; R v Steel [1981] 2 All ER 422,
where Lord Lane CJ stated that ‘the fact that the victim has died, despite or
because of medical treatment for the initial injury given by careful and skilled
medical practitioners, will not exonerate the original assailant from
responsibility for the death’. It is therefore clear that the medical
treatment, of itself, will not be held to have broken the chain of causation in
law. Wood and Mary could be charged with manslaughter on the basis of killing
by gross negligence, which, unlike unlawful act manslaughter, can be based on
an omission; see R v Lowe [1973] 1 All ER 805.
The key authority
regarding killing by gross negligence is the House of Lords’ ruling in R v
Adomako [1994] 3 All ER 79, where their Lordships held that an accused would be
guilty of manslaughter if the following four conditions were satisfi ed:
(i) The accused owed
a duty of care to the victim;
(ii) That duty was
broken;
(iii) The conduct of
the accused was grossly negligent;
(iv)That conduct
caused the victim’s death.
In some cases the
existence of a duty of care will be self-evident, for example doctor and
patient, parent and child etc. Notwithstanding the decision in R v Instan, it
should not be assumed that all familial relationships will give rise to a legal
duty of care, and in any event this would not assist as regards Mary. Significantly,
the Court of Appeal decision in R v Evans [2009] EWCA Crim 650, indicates that
a duty of care will be recognized by the courts in what might be referred to as
‘R v Miller’ situations—i.e., where the defendant has created a dangerous
situation and is aware, or ought reasonably to be aware, that this is the case.
Allowing Gloria’s physical condition to deteriorate and then not allowing her
back into the house might provide the evidential basis for this.
The trial judge in
the present case should direct that they can conclude that a duty of care
existed provided they find certain facts established—and the trial judge should
make clear to the jury what those key facts are. It is submitted that there is
sufficient evidence for the jury to conclude that a duty of care existed.
The breach of the
duty of care is evident in their not helping Gloria and not attempting to
obtain any alternative assistance for her—they did not even call the police to The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Commentary
Occasionally an exam
will contain a question that requires candidates to take a wider view of the
criminal law. This is such a question. Candidates cannot simply home in on a
specific area and cover it in detail. Candidates must try to think of instances
throughout the syllabus that can be used in your arguments to answer the
question. Avoid the common mistake of interpreting the question to read ‘Choose
one area of the criminal law where there are difficulties and write all about
them’! This question has been included as it enables candidates to think more
widely about the role of the criminal law within the legal system and society
as a whole. Providing a good answer requires the ability to take a broad view
of the syllabus—something candidates who revise topics in isolation are not
always able to do. Advise them of the problem. The issue of whether this breach
of the duty of care can be said to have caused the death of Gloria has already
been considered above.
The remaining live
issue, therefore, is that of gross negligence. Following the House of Lords’
decision in R v Adomako the jury will have to determine whether or not the accuser’s
conduct:
(a) departed from the
proper standard of care incumbent upon them;
(b) involved a risk
of death to the victim;
(c) was so grossly
negligent that it ought to be regarded as criminal.
As later cases such
as R v Mark and another [2004] All ER (D) 35 (Oct) indicate, actual foresight
of risk of death by the accused is not required. The test for mens rea is objective—does
the jury regard the act or omission leading to the breach of duty as being so
culpable that it should be labelled as ‘criminal’? Evidence that the defendants
knew they would cause harm by not acting is admissible to establish the
required fault, but is not essential. Similarly, evidence that Mary and Wood
had never thought about what might happen to Gloria could be admissible to show
that they should not be labeled as criminals, but such evidence would not
preclude a fi nding by the jury that they
had acted, or failed to act, in a manner that was grossly negligent.
Critically analyse
with reference to decided cases, the reasons why the development and
application of the criminal law is often unpredictable and inconsistent. The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Answer plan
• Constant change—R v
R [1991]
• Lack of
code—Caldwell [1981], Morgan [1975]
• Logic v policy
• Role of House of
Lords—Clegg [1995]
Suggested answer
The development of
many areas of law follows a consistent and logical course. The basic
foundations, their concepts and application are accepted by the vast majority,
and only fine tuning or adjustments of these principles are required to meet
new situations. Unfortunately this cannot be said about criminal law, where the
debate about fundamental concepts—such as whether recklessness should be
interpreted subjectively or objectively; whether a mistake of fact relied upon
by a defendant should have to be one that a reasonable person would have made;
whether duress should be a defenses to a charge of murder—is still ongoing.
One of the problems
is that the criminal law is subject to constant change. It has to adapt to
cover new phenomena, such as stalking, drug abuse, and internet fraud and to
reflect society’s changing social and moral standards. As the House of Lords
stated in R v R [1991] 4 All ER 481, abolishing the husband’s marital rape
exemption, the common law is capable of evolving in the light of social, economic
and cultural developments. In that case the recognition that the status of
women had changed out of all recognition from the time (Hale’s Pleas of the
Crown 1736) when the husband’s marital rape exemption was initially recognized
was long overdue. Similarly, the criminal law once reflected the moral position
that it was a crime to take one’s own life. Failure in such an enterprise was
prosecuted as attempted suicide and could be punished. However, attitudes
softened and it was recognized that such a person needed help, not a criminal
trial; the law was consequently amended by the Suicide Act 1961. The 1960s saw similar
changes in respect of the law relating to homosexuality and abortion. Changes in
the law can also result from a shift in ideology on the part of an elected
government, or as a response to new threats to the safety and stability of
society—for example legislation to combat terrorism. There is no doubt that the
development and application of the criminal law would be more consistent and
predictable if the courts exhibited a more uniform approach to its development.
The problem is illustrated by two House of Lords’ decisions:
Metropolitan Police
Commissioner v Caldwell [1981] 1 All ER 961, where an objective approach to
recklessness was used, and DPP v Morgan [1975] 2 All ER 347, where a subjective
approach to mistake was applied. Why it was that liability for recklessness was
imposed on an objective basis, but where a defendant made a mistake of fact he The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea was entitled (subject to any
statutory provision to the contrary) to be judged on the facts as he honestly
believed them to be? Commentators may argue that two different areas of the
criminal law were being considered, criminal damage and rape (note that the law
has since been changed as regards rape by the Sexual Offences Act 2003), but
the inconsistency is still stark. At least in so far as recklessness is
concerned, the House of Lords has now embraced the notion of subjectivity again
in R v G [2003] 4 All ER 765, but the very fact that the legal definition of
such a basic concept can change so much in the space of 20 years is itself
startling.
The Law Commission
has long argued that the solution lies in codifying the law (see Law Com. No.
143) on the basis that: ‘the criminal law could then exhibit a uniform approach
to all crimes and defenses’.
All other major
European countries (France, Germany, and Spain) have a detailed criminal code,
with a uniform approach providing a starting point for interpreting the law.
The criminal law in England and Wales has developed in a piecemeal fashion,
with one offence’s development showing little consistency with another’s. So
often it is difficult to say what our law actually is, even before lawyers
start to debate how it should be applied, e.g., R v Savage; R v Parmenter
[1992] 1 AC 699, interpreting (after over 130 years of use) the provisions of
the Offences Against the Person Act 1861. A code could be expressed in clear
language with definitions of fundamental concepts such as intention and
recklessness, as suggested by the Law Commission’s Draft Criminal Code; although,
as the former chairman of the Law Commission Justice Henry Brooke stated ([1995]
Crim LR 911): ‘Nobody in their right mind would want to put the existing
criminal law into a codified form’.
Often the criminal
law follows a logical approach in its application; but as it does not exist in
a vacuum and is not simply the application of academic principles, policy considerations
sometimes have to prevail. As Lord Salmon stated in DPP v Majewski [1976] 2 All
ER 142, regarding the defence of intoxication, ‘the answer is that in strict logic
the view [intoxication is no defenses to crimes of basic intent] cannot be
justified. But this is the view that has been adopted by the common law which
is founded on common sense and experience rather than strict logic’. Policy
considerations are also behind s. 1(3) of the Criminal Attempts Act 1981,
whereby in the offence of attempt, the facts are to be as the accused believes
them to be. Thus an accused, objectively viewed, may appear not to be
committing a criminal act but because they believe they are, they can be guilty
of attempting to commit that criminal act, as in R v Shivpuri [1986] 2 All ER
334.
There is often no
means of predicting which approach will prevail. In Jaggard v Dickinson [1980]
3 All ER 716, the accused, who had been informed by her friend X that she could
break into X’s house to shelter, while drunk mistakenly broke into V’s house.
She was charged with criminal damage under s. 1(1) of the Criminal Damage Act 1971,
but argued that she had a lawful excuse under s. 5(2) of the Act as she
honestly believed that she had the owner’s consent. Although the prosecution
contended that this was a crime of basic intent and therefore drunkenness was
no defence (citing the The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
House of Lords’
decisions of Metropolitan Police Commissioner v Caldwell and DPP v Majewski in
support), the Court of Appeal quashed her conviction, giving priority to the
statutory provision of s. 5(2) of the 1971 Act. One important aspect of the
criminal law process in recent years, which has caused uncertainty, is the role
of the House of Lords in changing the criminal law. Clearly judges are there to
say what the law is, not what it should be; but Lord Simon in DPP for Northern
Ireland v Lynch [1975] 1 All ER 913 said: ‘I am all for recognizing that judges
do make law. And I am all for judges exercising their responsibilities boldly
at the proper time and place…where matters of social policy are not involved
which the collective wisdom of Parliament is better suited to resolve’. Thus in
R v R, the House of Lords changed the law of rape, by abolishing the husband’s
defence of marital rape immunity without waiting for Parliament to implement
the Law Commission’s recommendations. However, their Lordships took the opposite
view in R v Clegg [1995] 1 All ER 334, where they refused to follow the Law Commission’s
suggestion that a person who was entitled to use force in self-defense but who
used unreasonable force, thereby killing the victim, would be guilty of manslaughter,
not murder. Lord Lloyd stated:
I am not adverse to
judges developing law, or indeed making new law, when they can see their way
clearly, even where questions of social policy are involved. [A good example is
R v R.] But in the present case I am in no doubt that your Lordships should
abstain from law making. The reduction of what would otherwise be murder to
manslaughter in a particular class of case seems to me essentially a matter for
decision by the legislature. It is difficult to appreciate the essential
difference in issues in these two cases, despite Lord Lowry’s justifications in
R v Clegg that ‘R v R dealt with a specific act and not with a general
principle governing criminal liability’. Clearly there is a difference in
opinion amongst the Law Lords as to the correct application of these
principles. This is well illustrated by the House of Lords’ decision in R v
Gotts [1992] 1 All ER 832. The majority decision not to allow duress as a
defence to attempted murder was on the basis that duress was no defence to
murder. The minority view to the contrary revealed a different analysis. They
argued that duress is a general defence throughout the criminal law with the
exceptions of the offences of murder and treason. It is for Parliament, and not
the courts, to limit the ambit of a defence; and as attempted murder is a
different offence to murder, duress must therefore be available. It is
submitted that these are the main reasons why the development and application of
the criminal law is often uncertain and unpredictable. There are other factors,
such as whether an issue is a question of law for the judge or fact for the
jury, e.g., the meaning of ‘administer’ (R v Gillard (1988) 87 Cr App R 189);
the difficulty in ascertaining the ratio decided of many cases, e.g., R v Brown
[1993] 2 All ER 75 (consent); and the possible effect of the decisions of the
European Court of Human Rights. But it is the lack of a code and uniform
principles which are the main factors causing the inherent uncertainty.The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Commentary
Liability for
omissions is a popular topic with examiners, either as an element of a problem question—typically
linked to killing by gross negligence to bring out the duty of care issues—or
as an essay topic in its own right. To deal comfortably with essay-style
questions on omissions it is necessary to have a good knowledge of the basic
cases. For degree level examinations, however, it is likely that some element
of analysis will be necessary. The extent to which this is the case will vary
according to the level at which the paper is set. Second and third year undergraduates
and CPE students would be expected to display more developed skills of critical
evaluation. Try to avoid simply describing the law—ensure that some comment is
provided on the examples given. There is not a great deal of material on law
reform in this area—the Law Commission has not explored it in great detail, but
it should not be difficult to identify some of the anomalies that the case law
throws up. For a flowchart on liability for failing to act,
Answer plan
• Basic rule on
liability for omissions
• Legal duty based on
statute
• Legal duty based on
contract
• Legal duty based on
office
• Common law duty to
act
• Where a duty ceases
to exist
• Possible reforms
Question 6
Critically assess the
grounds upon which liability for failing to act will be imposed in English criminal
law.
Suggested answer
Every offence in
criminal law requires proof of an actus reus on the part of the accused. In the
vast majority of cases statute or common law defi nes this actus reus in terms of a positive
act. Indeed, the expression actus reus literally translates as ‘guilty act’. A
The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea moment’s thought reveals,
however, that a defendant can commit an offence by failing to act, just as
readily as he can by positive action. If the parents of a newly born baby
administer a lethal dose of poison to the child no one would seriously suggest
that there would be a problem in establishing actus reus. Why should it be any
different where the defendants decide not to feed the child, with the result
that the child dies of starvation? The answer is that there is no difference in
criminal law, but the method by which liability is established may differ where
it is based on an omission as opposed to a positive act. The basic rule in English
criminal law is that there is no general positive duty to act to prevent the
commission of criminal offences or to limit the effect of harm caused by the
actions of others. This position reflects what is sometimes referred to as the
individualistic approach to liability. If D is at a swimming pool, and he sees
P (a young child with whom he has no connection) drowning in the deep end, why
should D be required to go to P’s aid? D has no special responsibility for P,
and did not cause the risk to arise. It is pure chance that D is in a position
to help. Why should fate be the basis for imposing a liability for failing to
prevent P’s death? Critics of the current position at common law argue for a
‘social responsibility’ approach. This view proposes that liability should
arise for failing to attend those in peril partly because of the moral
obligation to do so, but also because it reflects a more complex social pact. A
positive duty to aid others would impose a responsibility but would also confer
a corresponding benefit. D might one day find himself compelled to help P, but
the next day he might be the benefi
ciary of the duty on P to aid D where D is in peril. At a macro level
society benefits because less harm is suffered by individuals. In reality
English criminal law does impose criminal liability for failing to act, but it does
so on the basis of exceptions. Thus D will not incur liability for failing to
act unless the prosecution can point to a positive legal duty to act.
The most obvious
source of such legal duties will be statute. Parliament creates liability for
failing to act in two ways. At a very simple level it creates offences of
omission. It is an offence for the owner of a vehicle to fail to display a
valid tax disc. It is an offence to fail to submit a tax return, or to provide
company accounts, etc. In these cases the omission itself is the crime. In many
cases they are offences of strict or absolute liability. Alternatively
Parliament may enact legislation that places a category of person under a duty
to act in a particular way. A failure to comply with this duty may result in
liability where the failure causes the commission of some prohibited
consequence. Perhaps the best known example of this is provided by the Children
and Young Persons Act 1933, which places parents and guardians under a legal
duty to care for children. Suppose that parents go out for the evening leaving
a four-year-old child alone. Whilst they are out he falls onto a fire and is
killed. It is likely that the court would find that there was a culpable
omission based on the breach of statutory duty, and liability could be imposed
if causation and fault are also established.
An alternative basis
for establishing a legal duty to act is where D is subject to a contractual
duty or holds an office that suggests the imposition of a duty. In the case of
employees the court will look at the express or implied terms of the contract
to determine The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea the extent and
nature of the duties imposed on D. In R v Pittwood (1902) 19 TLR 37, a railway
crossing gatekeeper opened the gate to let a cart pass, but then went off to
lunch, forgetting to close the gate. A hay cart crossed the line and was hit by
a train. The defendant was convicted of manslaughter. He argued that the only
duty he owed was to his employers, with whom he had a contract. It was held,
however, that his contract imposed a wider duty upon him to users of the
crossing. Thus the duty arising under a contract inures to the benefit of those
who are not privy to the contract—i.e., the passengers on the train. In R v
Dytham [1979] 3 All ER 641, D was a police constable on duty. He witnessed V
being ejected from a nightclub and beaten up by a doorman. D did not intervene.
V died from his injuries. D was convicted of the common law offence of
misfeasance in public office and his appeal against conviction was dismissed.
The case begs the question—why was D not charged with causing the death of V by
his failure to intervene? The answer may be that in cases of failing to act,
proof of causation may be problematic. D obviously failed in his duty as a
police officer—but would his intervention have prevented V’s death? The mere
fact that there is an agreement between parties does not necessarily mean that
there will be a contractual duty to act. In R v Instan [1893] 1 QB 450, D was
given money by her aunt to buy groceries. D failed to care for her aunt who
subsequently died. It is unlikely that any contractual duty existed in this case,
as the agreement was a domestic one—hence there would have been no intention to
create legal relations.
Inevitably there are
situations where, despite the absence of any statutory or contractual duty to
act, it is felt that liability ought to be imposed. In such cases it falls to
the common law to perform its residual function of supplying the omission.
Judges ‘discover’ new common law duties to act because it is felt they ought to
exist. R v Instan is a case in point. For the last 12 days of her life the aunt
was suffering from gangrene in her leg and was unable to look after herself.
Only D knew this. D did not provide her aunt with food nor did she obtain
medical attention. This omission accelerated the aunt’s death. D’s conviction
for manslaughter was upheld, the court proceeding on the basis that a common
law duty was simply a moral duty so fundamental the courts had to enforce it.
As Lord Coleridge CJ observed, a legal common law duty is nothing else than the
enforcing by law of that which is a moral obligation without legal enforcement.
The problem with the
common law is that it is reactive—it only develops because cases come to the
courts on appeal. A narrow reading of R v Instan suggests that a common law
duty is owed to one’s blood relatives, but clearly the scope should be wider than
that. The court in R v Gibbins and Proctor (1918) 13 Cr App R 134, accepted that
a duty could be imposed upon a common law wife to care for her partner’s child because,
although the child was not hers, she had assumed a duty towards the child by choosing
to live with the child’s father and accept housekeeping money to buy food for them
all. The problem with such rulings is that the limits of liability are left vague—what
if D had lived with the child’s father only on weekends? Imposing liability for
omissions where D undertakes to care for P and P becomes reliant on D may even
be counter-productive. In R v Stone and Dobinson [1977] QB 354, the defendants
were convicted of the manslaughter of Stone’s sister Fanny because they the
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens reatook her in but failed to care for
her adequately. With hindsight they might have been advised not to help her in
the fi rst place. The law therefore
sends mixed messages. One ought to care for others, but one should not start to
do so unless one is able to discharge that duty properly.
The common law duty
to act was developed further by the important House of Lords’ decision in R v
Miller [1983] 1 All ER 978. D, who was squatting in an empty house, fell asleep
whilst smoking a cigarette. Whilst he was asleep the cigarette set fire to the mattress.
D woke, realized the mattress was on fi
re, but took no steps to douse the fire. The house was damaged in the
ensuing blaze. He was obviously not under a statutory duty to put the fire out,
nor was he under a contractual duty to do so. At the time the common law duties
to act were based on duties owed to blood relatives, or arising from reliance.
The House of Lords had little choice but to ‘discover’ a new legal duty at
common law. Such a duty arises where D accidentally causes harm, realizes that
he has done so, and it lies within his power to take steps, either himself or by
calling for the assistance to prevent or minimize the harm. The omission itself
is not, of course, the offence. For criminal damage it must be shown that the
omission caused the harm, and that D had the requisite mens rea at the time of
the actus reus. The doctrine has since been applied to killing by gross
negligence in R v Evans (Gemma) [2009] EWCA 650, where it was held that
awareness of having caused a dangerous situation could of itself give rise to
the duty of care (effectively the duty to act) that forms the basis of the offence.
Whilst the ruling in R v Miller is socially desirable—there is great social
utility in D being required to limit the effect of his careless actions—there
are many uncertainties. What is it that D is required to do once he realizes he
has caused harm? Is the test objective or subjective? Must he act as the
reasonable person would have done, or does he simply have to do his best? The
latter would certainly accord with the general trend towards subjectivity in
criminal law.
Even where a positive
legal duty to act can be identified, uncertainties may arise as to whether D
has been or can be absolved from that duty. In R v Smith [1979] Crim LR 251,
D’s wife was seriously ill. She asked D not to seek help. Her condition
worsened and she eventually asked D to get help, which he did, but it was too
late to save her. D was charged with manslaughter and the trial judge directed
the jury that D was under a duty by virtue of being the victim’s husband, but
he could be released from that duty if she so indicated and she were of sound
mind at the time. This places the husband in a difficult legal position. At
what point must he ignore his wife’s wishes and obtain medical help? Some
clarification is provided by the House of Lords’ decision in Airedale NHS Trust
v Bland [1993] AC 789, where it was held that doctors were under a duty to
treat a patient where it was in the patient’s best interests to do so. Where,
however, all hope of the patient recovering had disappeared, the duty to nourish
and maintain the patient would also cease. To date the Law Commission has done
little more than suggest a codification of the common law position as outlined
above. It is submitted that a more radical approach would be to adopt the
French model of creating a general statutory duty of ‘easy rescue’. Essentially
there would be liability for failing to prevent harm where such prevention the
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea would not be too onerous or difficult
for D to achieve. The accident that led to the death of Princess Diana in the
Paris underpass illustrates the point. French photographers were charged with
manslaughter based on their failure to help because they allegedly photographed
the crash scene when they could have been offering aid to the injured. Such a
prosecution would not have been possible under English law.
Further reading Amirthalingam,
K., ‘Caldwell Recklessness is Dead, Long Live Mens Rea’s Fecklessness’ [2004]
MLR 491.Ashworth, A., ‘Interpreting Criminal Statutes’ [1991] LQR 419.Ashworth,
A. and Blake, M., ‘The Presumption of Innocence in English Criminal Law’ [1996]
Crim LR 306.Kaveny, C.M., ‘Inferring Intention from Foresight’ (2004) LQR
120.Keating, H., ‘Reckless Children?’ [2007] Crim LR 546.Norrie, A., ‘Oblique
Intent and Legal Politics’ [1989] Crim LR 793.Pedain, A., ‘Intention and the
Terrorist Example’ [2003] Crim LR 549.Smith, J.C., ‘R v Woollin’ [1998] Crim LR
890.
No comments:
Post a Comment