The elements of a crime actus reus
and mens rea.
Introduction
The traditional
starting point for the study of criminal law is the constituents of a criminal
offence: actus reus (often referred to as the prohibited conduct, but more
accurately described as the external elements of the offence) and mens rea
(often referred to as the mental element, but more accurately described as the
fault element). Commentators and students alike want to find consistency and
certainty in the application and development of the criminal law, and most
criminal law textbooks dealing with the elements of crimes try to state
principles that the student should see consistently applied in later chapters
covering specific offences. The main problem is that the offences have developed
in a piecemeal fashion, exhibiting no underlying rationale or common approach. Thus
in examining actus reus, the student might be covering an offence defi ned in modern terms, e.g., by the Criminal
Damage Act 1971, or in obscure outdated language, e.g., in the Offences Against
the Person Act 1861, or the definition of actus reus may arise from the common
law, perhaps amended or augmented by statute, e.g., murder. Similarly, when we
examine our approach to mens rea, we can see little common ground. If the offence
requires the prosecution to prove intention, this must generally be left to the
jury without detailed guidance from the trial judge (R v Moloney [1985]
1 All ER 1025); but
if recklessness is the issue, a direction spelling out to the jury what they
must find may be required. If one looks at the development of the concept of
recklessness one can see that, prior to the decision of the House of Lords in R
v G [2003] 4 All ER 765, a case involving criminal damage would have involved a
court in trying to assess whether the defendant was reckless according to the
definition laid down in Metropolitan Police Commissioner v Caldwell [1981] 1
All ER 961. Following the abandonment of ‘Caldwell recklessness’ in R v G [2003]
4 All ER 765, the issue has been simplifi
ed so that a court now has to concentrate on whether or not the
defendant was aware of the risk in question and if so, whether or not, in the
circumstances known to the defendant, it was unreasonable for him to take the
risk. If dishonesty is the mens rea
(see Theft Acts 1968–1996) the jury must consider two specific questions (would
ordinary people consider D dishonest?; if so, did D realize that they would?);
but these are questions of fact for them to resolve (R v Ghosh [1982] 2 All ER
689). In other words, there are three different approaches in establishing the
mens rea for different offences. A search for consistency is therefore a futile
exercise! Students should therefore be aware that studying the chapters on
actus reus and mens rea can produce a distorted impression of the criminal law.
One is dealing with concepts in isolation and could form the impression that
these general principles are consistently applied. One particular criticism is
that the criminal law is not consistent in applying objective or subjective
tests for liability. Objective tests consider what the reasonable person would
have foreseen. Subjective tests judge the defendant on the facts as he honestly
believed them to be. There appears to be an absence of any underlying rationale
and the offences develop independently of each other. One can understand why
Sir Henry Brooke (former head of the Law Commission) and many others wish for
codification of some, if not all, of the criminal law (see [1995] Crim LR
911—‘The Law Commission and Criminal Law Reform’). Even established concepts
that have been applied by the courts for many years, may suddenly come under
attack and be interpreted differently by the judiciary. Thus the House of Lords
in Attorney-General’s Reference (No. 3 of 1994) [1997] 3 All ER 936, reversed
the Court of Appeal decision ([1996] 2 WLR 412), holding that the doctrine of
transferred malice could not apply to convict an accused of murder when he
deliberately injured a pregnant woman in circumstances where the baby was born
alive but subsequently died. Lord Mustill criticized the doctrine as having no
sound intellectual basis and involving a fiction, although the Criminal Law Review
disagrees with his view ([1997] Crim LR 830). In this chapter questions have
been chosen to cover all major aspects of this area. There are some problem
questions, but candidates should expect the essay questions in an exam to be
selected from these topics. Essays are therefore included on the important aspects
of mens rea: intention and recklessness.
Question 1
The practice of
leaving the issue of intention to the jury without any judicial guidance as to
its meaning is unworkable and likely
to produce inconsistent decisions. Discuss this statement with reference to
decided cases.
Commentary
There have been so
many important decisions on this important aspect of criminal law, that it is
always likely to be the subject of an examination question. Because the facts of R v Moloney [1985] 1
All ER 1025 are so well known, there is a temp-
tation simply to
regurgitate them with the House of Lords’ decisions. This must be resisted as there
are many ingredients in the answer, which requires careful planning and
organization. In summary, this is a question where it is quite easy to obtain a
pass mark but difficult to obtain a high grade.
Answer plan
• Mens rea
• Intention—defi nition
• Moloney [1985]—‘the
golden rule’
• Woollin
[1998]—direction on intention
• Law Commission No.
218
Suggested answer
Except with strict
(or absolute) liability offences, in order for an accused to be found Except with strict (or absolute) liability
offences, in order for an accused to be found guilty of a criminal offence, the
prosecution must prove that the accused committed the actus reus of the offence
with the appropriate mens rea. Mens rea generally signifies blameworthiness,
although in R v Kingston [1994] 3 All ER 353, the House of Lords confirmed that
the accused was guilty of an offence requiring the prosecution to prove
intention, although he was morally blameless. Mens rea is the mental element, which
varies from one offence to another; but generally, for the more serious
offences, it comprises intention or recklessness, with intention being reserved
for the most serious crimes.
One would therefore
think that, being of such fundamental importance, intention would be
specifically defined and rigidly applied, but this is not the case. There have
always been difficulties with the concept of intention within the criminal law.
What is it? How should it be defined? How does the prosecution prove it? How
does the trial judge direct the jury? These issues have been the subject of
much judicial and academic debate in recent years. Although the word
‘intention’ implies purpose or even desire, there have been many diverse definitions
by the judiciary, and commentators have also identified different types of
intention. First, direct intent, where it was the accuser’s purpose or motive
to bring about a result. Thus in R v Steane [1947] 1 All ER 813, the accused,
who assisted the enemy during the war, had his conviction quashed as the court
decided that he did not intend to assist the enemy; he intended to protect his
family, who would have been harmed had he not cooperated. Secodly, oblique intent,
where the accused does not necessarily desire the result but foresees it as
highly probable. Thus in Hyam v DPP [1974] 2 All ER 41, the House of Lords
upheld a conviction for murder where the .
The elements of a
crime: actus reus and mens re accused had set fire to the victim’s house even
though the accused’s purpose had been only to frighten the victim. Because
there was evidence that the accused foresaw that death or grievous bodily harm
was highly probable the House of Lords felt justified in concluding that her
state of mind could be regarded as a form of intent (on this matter the law is
now as set out in R v Woollin [1998] 4 All ER 103—see below). Thirdly, ulterior
intent, where it must be shown that in intentionally doing one act the accused
has a related purpose. Thus to be guilty of burglary under s. 9(1)(a) of the
Theft Act 1968, it is necessary for the prosecution to prove that the accused,
when deliberately entering a building as a trespasser, did so with a specific c related purpose in mind, e.g., to steal or commit
criminal damage. It would not be suffi
cient if the accused intentionally broke into the house with the sole
purpose of sheltering from the weather. The terms specific and basic intent,
are also used in respect of the defense of intoxication to distinguish between
those offences where intoxication is permitted as a defence and those where it is
not (see further DPP v Majewski [1976] 2 All ER 142). Although there is an
overlap between intentions on the one hand and motive and foresight on the
other, and these latter concepts assist the jury in their deliberations on intention,
it is clear that the concepts are not synonymous. Motive is the reason why a person
acts, while intention is his or her mental awareness at the time of the act.
Foresight can be evidence of intention, but it is not conclusive proof of it.
Section 8 of the Criminal Justice Act 1967 states that a court shall not be bound
in law to infer that the accused intended or foresaw a result of his actions by
reason only of its being a natural and probable consequence of those actions,
but ‘shall decide whether he did intend or foresee that result by reference to
all the evidence, drawing such inferences from the evidence as appear proper in
the circumstances’. The issue of intention was debated by the House of Lords in
R v Moloney [1985] 1 All ER 1025 and R v Hancock and Shankland [1986] 1 All ER
641. In the former case, Maloney shot his stepfather from point blank range and
was convicted of murder after the trial judge (following Archbold Criminal
Pleading Evidence and Practice, 40th edn, para. 17–13, p. 995) directed the
jury that: In law a man intends the consequence of his voluntary act:
(a) When he desires
it to happen, whether or not he foresees that it probably will happen, or
(b) When he foresees
that it will probably happen, whether he desires it or not.
The House of Lords
quashed the conviction on the basis that this was misdirection, Lord Bridge
stating that: the golden rule should be that, when directing a jury on the
mental element necessary in a crime of specific intent (i.e., intention), the
judge should avoid any elaboration or paraphrase of what is meant by intent,
and leave it to the jury’s good sense to decide whether the accused acted with
the necessary intent, unless the judge is convinced that, on the facts and
having regard to the way the case has been presented to the jury in evidence
and argument, some further explanation or elaboration is strictly necessary to
avoid misunderstanding.
Although the decision
may be criticized on the ground that their Lordships missed a golden
opportunity to define intention, it is in keeping with the modern trend of
leaving more and more issues to the jury, especially the meaning of words in
common use.
For example, Brutus v
Cozens [1972] 2 All ER 1297 (insulting); R v Feely [1973] 1 All ER 341
(dishonestly). This decision was followed by the House of Lords’ ruling in R v
Hancock and Shankland, where Lord Scarman also made the point that if intention
required a detailed direction it was best to leave this to the discretion of
the trial judge who would have had the benefit of hearing all the witnesses and
gauging the ability of the jury. He added that the trial judge could not do as
Lord Bridge suggested and simply direct the jury to consider two questions: first,
was death or really serious injury in a murder case a natural consequence of
the defendant’s voluntary act?; secondly, did the defendant foresee that
consequence as being a natural consequence of his act?—further instructing them
that if they answer ‘Yes’ to both questions it is a proper inference for them
to draw that the accused intended that consequence. Lord Scarman stated that
the trial judge must refer to the concept of probability—the more probable the
consequence, the more likely the accused foresaw it and intended it. Despite
clear House of Lords’ dicta to the contrary, the Court of Appeal in R v Nedrick
[1986] 3 All ER 1 did lay down some guidelines to the effect that the jury
should not infer intention unless they considered that the accused foresaw the
consequence as a virtual certainty. However, this decision has attracted criticism,
and the Court of Appeal in R v Walker and Hayles [1989] 90 Cr App R 226 stated
‘we are not persuaded that it is only when death is a virtual certainty that
the jury can infer intention to kill’.
Nevertheless, the
status of Nedrick was confirmed by the House of Lords’ discussion in R v
Woollin [1998] 4 All ER 103. The House, stating that where the simple direction
was not enough, the jury should be further directed that they were not entitled
to find the necessary intention unless they felt sure that death or serious
bodily harm was a virtually certain result of D’s action (barring some unforeseen
intervention) and, that D had appreciated that fact.
This decision also
illustrates one of the difficulties of the present approach, i.e., when is the
issue of intention so complicated as to warrant a detailed direction? In R v
Walker and Hayles, the Court of Appeal decided that ‘the mere fact that a jury
calls for a further direction on intention does not of itself make it a rare
and exceptional case requiring a foresight direction’. On the other hand, in R
v Hancock and Shankland, the House of Lords confirmed that the trial judge was
right to give a detailed direction, even though the content of the direction
was wrong. A further problem is that different juries may have different ideas
as to what constitutes intention, some insisting on purpose being necessary,
while others are prepared to accept that only foresight of a probable
consequence is required. There is clearly the
The elements of a
crime: actus reus and mens rea
Commentary
This question
requires examination of some of the assumptions made about mens rea and the
current trends in judicial thinking. Candidates would be expected to consider
the main forms of mens rea and the extent to which courts are required to take
an objective or subjective view of fault. Although ‘Caldwell recklessness’ has
now been effectively consigned to legal history (for the time being at least) a
good answer will need to show an awareness of that decision and its impact on
the mens rea debate. Consideration also needs to be given to the issue of
mistake and its relationship with mens rea. Finally, the answer should encompass
some consideration of negligence as a form of mens rea and the extent to which
its use accords with notions of subjective fault.
Answer plan
• The nature of mens
rea
• Intention—R v
Woollin— House of Lords’ decision
• The recklessness
debate R v G [2003]—abandoning Caldwell
• The treatment of
mistake and its effect on mens rea—DPP v Morgan [1976]
• Killing by gross
negligence—whether objective or subjective
risk of inconsistent
decisions and it is therefore not surprising that the Law Commission
(Nos 122 and 218)
have recommended that the following standard defi nition of inten-
tion be adopted:
a person acts
intentionally with respect to a result when
(i) It is his purpose
to cause it; or
(ii) Although it is
not his purpose to cause that result, he knows that it would occur in the
ordinary course of events if he were to succeed in his purpose of causing some other
result.
Question 2
‘Mens rea is, by
defi nition, the defendant’s state of
mind.’
Discuss the accuracy
of this statement using case law to support your argument.
The elements of a
crime: actus reus and mens rea
Suggested answer
Although mens rea
translates literally as ‘guilty mind’, relying on this as the meaning given to
that term in modern criminal law is likely to lead to error. This is because a defendant
may be found to have mens rea even though he himself has not acted with the
intention of committing an offence, or even with the awareness that this might
be the result. The better approach is to regard mens rea as denoting the fault
element that the prosecution has to prove. In the majority of cases this will
involve proof of some positive state of mind on the part of the accused, but in
other cases it may be enough to show that the accused failed to advert to
something that would have been obvious to the reasonable person.
The two most
important fault elements used in modern criminal law are intention and
recklessness. It can now be said that, as far as these two forms of mens rea
are concerned, liability cannot be established without evidence as to what the
defendant foresaw when he committed the acts causing the prohibited results.
Exactly what it is that the defendant has to have foreseen, and how much
foresight he must be shown to have had, are questions that go to the core of
the debate relating to where the dividing line between different types of
subjective mens rea should be drawn. The modern definition of intention can be
derived from a number of House of Lords’ decisions, notably R v Moloney [1985]
1 All ER 1025 and R v Woollin [1998] 4 All ER 103. A defendant cannot be guilty
of murder unless he is proved to have acted with intent to kill or do grievous
bodily harm. Where a direction on intent is deemed necessary, a jury should be
instructed that they should consider the extent to which the defendant foresaw
death or grievous bodily harm resulting from his actions. Only where there is evidence
that he foresaw either consequence as virtually certain would it be safe for a jury
to conclude that a defendant therefore intended either of those consequences.
The key here is foresight. Section 8 of the Criminal Justice Act 1967 makes
clear that foresight is a subjective concept—i.e., it is based on what the
defendant actually foresaw not on what he ought to have foreseen, or indeed
what the reasonable person would have foreseen had he been in the defendant’s shoes.
Taken together, the definition of foresight in the 1967 Act, and the House of
Lords’ ruling in Woollin ensure that where intention is the required mens rea,
there can be no doubt that it will be based on the defendant’s state of
mind—i.e., a subjective approach will be adopted.
The rationale for
this is fairly obvious—it is hard to describe a defendant as having intended a
consequence if there is no evidence of it having occurred to him. Even where there
is such evidence, if the possibility of the consequence occurring has only
fl eetingly crossed his mind it would
still be absurd to say he intended it. The law, therefore, requires a very high
degree of foresight before a defendant’s state of mind is labeled as having
been intentional.
Recklessness, by
contrast, implies risk taking, as opposed to the defendant foreseeing a
consequence as a certainty. Here there has been great controversy over the past
few.
The elements of a
crime: actus reus and mens rea decades as to the right approach to the
determination of fault. The traditional approach to recklessness as a form of
mens rea very much reflected the view that mens rea had to be based on the
defendant’s state of mind. In R v Cunningham [1957] 2 All ER 412, the Court of
Appeal held that a defendant was reckless only if he took an unjustifiable risk
and was at least aware of the risk materializing. The key point about this
approach to recklessness was that there would be no liability if the risk never
occurred to the defendant.
Subsequently, during
the 1980s a contrary view held sway, following the House of Lords’ decision in
Metropolitan Police Commissioner v Caldwell [1981] 1 All ER 961. D’s conviction
for criminal damage being reckless as to whether life would be endangered,
contrary to s. 1(1) of the Criminal Damage Act 1971, was upheld on the basis that
he had created an obvious risk that property would be destroyed or damaged; and
had either given no thought to the possibility of there being any such risk, or
had recognized that there was some risk involved and had nevertheless gone on
to do it. The ‘not thinking’ formulation of recklessness here, clearly
envisaged liability being imposed even though the risk in question had not occurred
to the defendant. Whilst this might have been a desirable policy goal—it made
it easier for the prosecution to secure convictions—it threw up many difficult
issues. First, what of the defendant who did not think of the risk because it
would not have occurred to him even if he had stopped to think? In Elliot v C
(A Minor) [1983] 2 All ER 1005, a 14-year-old schoolgirl of low intelligence, who
was tired and hungry, spilt some infl
ammable spirit and then dropped a lighted match on the wooden floor of a
garden shed. She was charged under s. 1(1) of the Criminal Damage Act 1971. It
was argued that she did not foresee the risk of fi re, nor would she had she addressed her mind
to the possible consequences of her action. Although Goff LJ stated that a test
for recklessness which allowed the court to take into account the individual
characteristics of the accused had much merit (a subjective approach), he felt
bound by the doctrine of precedent (at that time) to follow Caldwell, and
therefore concluded that the defendant should have convicted on the objective
test basis, i.e., whether the risk would have been obvious to a reasonable man.
Secondly, there was the argument that ‘Caldwell recklessness’ was not
acceptable as a form of mens rea because it was not based on the defendant’s
state of mind. In R v Reid [1992] 3 All ER 673, Lord Keith observed by way of
response that: ‘Absence of something from a person’s state of mind is as much
part of his state of mind as is its presence. Inadvertence to risk is no less a
subjective state of mind than is disregard of a recognized risk.’ What he meant
by this was that even with ‘Caldwell recklessness’, the court had to consider
the defendant’s state of mind. But, it is submitted, this is a piece of judicial
sophistry, as all that was required was for the court to examine the
defendant’s state of mind and, on fi
nding ‘no thought’, conclude that he had been reckless provided the risk
would have been obvious to the reasonable prudent bystander. Whilst many might
have applauded Lord Diplock’s efforts to penalize thoughtless-ness in terms of
a social policy initiative, the real question was whether he was right to The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea pursue this via a radical judicial
reinterpretation of the term ‘recklessness’. It is significant that Parliament
intervened shortly after Caldwell to reform the offence of reckless driving
(and therefore causing death by reckless driving) by replacing it with the offence
of dangerous driving—see the Road Traffic Act 1991. The effect of this was to
make clear that the offence could now be committed without any form of mens rea
that required reference to the defendant’s state of mind. Recklessness was
replaced, as a fault element, by the term ‘dangerous’. Whilst it could and was
argued that recklessness implied some conscious risk-taking by the accused,
there was no doubt that ‘dangerousness’ as a fault element rested entirely upon
an objective assessment of the defendant’s conduct. In other words a defendant
could drive dangerously because he had a badly secured load on the back of his
trailer—there was no need for him to be aware of this. In summary this suggests
that Parliament liked the idea of criminal liability based on failure to think
about risk, but was not comfortable with the idea that ‘traditional’ mens rea
terms like ‘recklessness’ might be used to describe it. As far as recklessness
is concerned the subjectivist argument has found favour again, as evidenced by
the House of Lords’ decision in R v G [2003] 4 All ER 765, where it was held
that a defendant could not be properly convicted under s. 1 of the Criminal Damage
Act 1971 on the basis that he was reckless as to whether property was destroyed
or damaged when he gave no thought to the risk and, by reason of his age and/or
personal characteristics, the risk would not have been obvious to him, even if
he had thought about it. Lord Bingham observed that recklessness should at
least require a knowing disregard of an appreciated and unacceptable risk of,
or a deliberate closing of the mind to, such risk. In his view it was not
clearly blameworthy to do something involving a risk of injury to another if
one genuinely did not perceive the risk. R v G reflects a general judicial
trend in favour of subjectivity, as evidenced in decisions such as B v DPP
[2000] 1 All ER 833. Indeed, the high watermark of this approach to fault was
the House of Lords’ decision in DPP v Morgan [1976] AC 182, where it was held
that if a defendant made a genuine mistake of fact—such as wrongly believing
that a woman was consenting to sexual intercourse, he had to be judged on the
facts as he believed them to be, not as the reasonable person would have
believed them to be. Lord Hailsham made it clear that there was no room either
for a ‘defense’ of honest belief or mistake, or of a defence of honest and
reasonable belief or mistake. The reasonableness of the defendant’s honest
belief was simply a factor relating to its credibility. The mental element in
the offence of rape has now been modifi ed
by the Sexual Offences Act 2003, so that rape is effectively now an offence
with a fault element based on negligence. The rationale of DPP v Morgan
survives, however, at common law to the extent that a defendant should normally
be judged on the facts as he honestly believes them to be.
As has been noted
above in the case of dangerous driving, fault elements that do not require
reference to the defendant’s state of mind are used. At common law this can be seen
in the offence of killing by gross negligence. In R v Adomako [1994] 3 WLR 288,
Lord Mackay LC explained that liability would be established if the prosecution
could prove that the defendant’s conduct departed from the proper standard of
care incumbent The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Commentary
This is an unusual
question which has caused students diffi
culties, with many writing about the offence of criminal damage. This is
a mistake as the question requires a detailed analysis of the mens rea
requirement of the Ancient Book Act 2009, and in particular analysis of the concept
of strict liability. In a survey by Justice referred to in an article by A.
Ashworth and M. Blake, ‘The Presumption of Innocence in English Criminal Law’
[1996] Crim LR 306, it is estimated that in over one half of criminal offences
either strict liability is imposed, or the prosecution have the benefit of a
presumption. It is obviously an important topic, and popular with examiners! A
good answer will require a detailed consideration of the possibility of this offence
being one of strict liability and the effect of this. Candidates should also
consider the position if the courts decide that intention or recklessness is
the appropriate mental state. upon him, thereby creating a risk of death, and
involved such a departure from accept-able standards of care as to deserve the
stigma of criminalization. As was made clear in Attorney-General’s Reference
(No. 2 of 1999) [2000] 3 All ER 182, evidence of the defendant’s state of mind
might be useful in guiding a jury as to whether or not the negligence was
gross, but this fault element can be made out without any direct evidence as to
the defendant’s state of mind. Whilst this may seem to run counter to the trend
in favors of subjectivity it should be remembered that it serves a useful
social purpose in making it easier to impose criminal liability on companies
that kill. In summary, therefore, it is undoubtedly true to say that mens rea
normally does involve an examination of the defendant’s state of mind to
ascertain a degree of awareness of the consequences of his actions. The law
will, however, allow departures from this where the social utility of doing so
outweighs the need to ensure the fairness to the defendant that ensues from
adopting a subjective approach to fault.
Question 3
You are told that the
(fi ctitious) Ancient Book Act 2009 has
just received the Royal Assent and that s. 1 provides, ‘It shall be an offence
to destroy any book printed before 1800’. Discuss the criminal liability of
each party (in relation to the 2009 Act) in the following situation.
Arthur owns 200
books, which he thinks are worthless. He is concerned in case any of the books
were printed before 1800 and consults Ben, an expert on old books, who assures
him that all the books were printed long after 1800. Arthur destroys the books
and is now horrifi ed to discover that
three of them were printed in 1750.The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens
rea
Answer plan
• Strict
liability—Sweet v Parsley [1969]
• Presumption of mens
rea—B v DPP [2000]
• The exceptions
• Recklessness
• Mistake—Morgan
[1976]
• Ben’s liability
under the Serious Crime Act 2007
Suggested answer
The first point to
note is that s. 1 of the Ancient Book Act 2009 is silent as to the mens rea
requirement of the offence. This could mean that the offence is one of absolute
liability (i.e., strict liability in the sense that no mens rea whatsoever is
required). Alternatively it could be a strict liability offence in the sense
that intention, recklessness or negligence is only required as regards one or
more elements of the actus reus. The imposition of absolute liability may be
very harsh on the defendant. For example, in Pharmaceutical Society of Great
Britain v Storkwain [1986] 2 All ER 635, the House of Lords upheld the conviction
of a pharmacist who had given drugs to a patient with a forged doctor’s prescription,
although the court found the pharmacist blameless. Whilst the decision demonstrates
the inherent unfairness of strict liability, it can be justifi ed on the basis that the misuse of drugs is a
grave social evil and therefore should be prevented at all costs.
The first case of
statutory strict liability was R v Woodrow (1846) 15 M & W 404, where the
accused was found guilty of being in possession of adulterated tobacco, even though
he did not know that it was adulterated. Many early decisions revealed an in-consistent
approach as the courts were trying to interpret old statutes in ascertaining the
will of Parliament. However, Lord Reid in the House of Lords’ decision in Sweet
v Parsley [1969] 1 All ER 347 laid down the following guidelines:
(a) Wherever a
section is silent as to mens rea there is a presumption that, in order to give
effect to the will of Parliament, words importing mens rea must be read into
the provision.
(b) It is a universal
principle that if a penal provision is reasonably capable of two
interpretations, that interpretation which is most favourable to the accused
must be adopted.
(c) The fact that
other sections of the Act expressly require mens rea is not in itself sufficient
to justify a decision that a section which is silent as to mens rea creates an
absolute offence. It is necessary to go outside the Act and examine all relevant
circumstances in order to establish that this must have been the intention of
Parliament.
The elements of a
crime: actus reus and mens rea So in Cundy v Le Coq (1884) 13 QB 207, a
publican was found guilty of selling intoxicating liquor to a drunken person
under s. 13 of the Licensing Act 1872, even though the publican did not know
and had no reason to know that the customer was drunk; whereas in Sherras v De
Rutzen [1895] 1 QB 918, a publican was not guilty under s. 16(2) of the
Licensing Act 1872 of serving alcohol to a police constable while on duty when
the accused did not know or have reason to know that the police constable was
on duty. The former case was held to be an offence of strict liability, whereas
in the latter, in order to obtain a conviction, the prosecution had to prove
mens rea on behalf of the publican, which they were unable to do.Despite the
fact that there is a presumption in favour of mens rea when a statute is silent,
the courts have been prepared to rebut this presumption on many occasions. The leading
case on this point is Gammon v Attorney-General for Hong Kong [1985] AC 1, where
Lord Scarman set out the applicable principles. If the offence is truly
criminal in character the presumption is particularly strong, but it can be
displaced where the statute is concerned with an issue of social concern. Thus,
in Gammon, as the accused’s activities involved public safety, the Privy
Council were prepared to hold that the legis-lature intended the offence to be
one of strict liability.
On analysis these
principles appear inconsistent. It could be argued that all crimes by definition
are grave social evils, yet if the offence is truly criminal in character,
strict liability does not apply. In practice, the courts have adopted a flexible
approach, but it is recognized that certain spheres of activity are always
likely to attract the conclusion that this is an offence of strict liability.
Thus inflation (R v St Margaret’s Trust Ltd [1958] 2 All ER 289), pollution
(Alphacell Ltd v Woodward [1972] 2 All ER 475), and dangerous drugs
(Pharmaceutical Society of Great Britain v Storkwain, above) are traditional areas
where strict liability has been imposed. However, it does seem in recent years that
the category of grave social concern is expanding to encompass new social
activity to include acting as a director whilst disqualifi ed (R v Brockley [1994] Crim LR 671) and unauthorized
possession of a dangerous dog (R v Bezzina [1994] 1 WLR 1057). However, the
House of Lords have again emphasized the need for the prosecution to prove mens
rea in B (A minor) v DPP [2000] 1 All ER 833, where Lord Hutton stated (at p.
855), ‘the test is not whether it is a reasonable implication that the statute rules
outmens rea as a constituent part of the crime—the test is whether it is a
necessary implication’. Further in R v Lambert [2001] 3 All ER 577, the House
held that although s. 28 of the Misuse of Drugs Act 1971 required the defence
to prove a defence, this only meant introduce evidence of, rather than
establish a defence on the balance of probabilities.
In view of these
developments, it is submitted that it would be most unlikely for s. 1 of the
Ancient Book Act 2009 to be an offence of strict liability, and therefore
Arthur will only be guilty if the prosecution can establish that he had the
necessary mens rea. As Rix LJ observed in R v M [2009] EWCA 2615, even if the
provision in question is silent as to mens rea and other provisions in the
statute expressly require it, the presumption in The elements of a crime: actus
reus and mens rea favour of mens rea will not be rebutted unless the
circumstances are such as to compel such a conclusion. If the court were to
decide that the offence required the prosecution to prove intention, it is
submitted that Arthur would not be convicted. He obtained the opinion of Ben,
an expert and clearly did not desire or even foresee the consequence that
protected books would be destroyed. Arthur has made a mistake, and even if an
accused makes an unreasonable mistake, in accordance with the House of Lords’
decision in DPP v Morgan [1976] AC 182, he is, in the absence of any clear
statutory intent to the contrary, entitled to be judged on the facts as he
believed them to be. If the court decides that the offence could be committed
recklessly, it would still be very difficult for the prosecution to establish
the appropriate mens rea. It is almost certainly the case that subjective
recklessness would have to be proved—i.e., the prosecution must show that the
accused foresaw the consequence and took an unjustified risk (R v Cunningham
[1957] 2 All ER 412 and R v G [2003] 4 All ER 765) (although technically the
latter only deals with the issue of recklessness in relation to criminal damage).
As Arthur sought the opinion of an expert it is diffi cult to see how it could
be argued that he was consciously taking an unjustified risk. It is therefore
submitted that Arthur could be guilty of the offence only if the court decides
that s. 1 of the Ancient Book Act 2009 creates an offence of strict liability.
Turning to Ben’s
liability, if he genuinely believed the books to be of post-1800 vintage and
the courts interpret the offence as requiring at least recklessness on this
issue, he could not be convicted as an accomplice as he would lack the
necessary mens rea. If the offence were held to be one of strict or absolute
liability Ben could only be convicted as an accomplice if he knew of the facts
that constituted the offence—i.e. he knew the books dated from before 1800—see
Johnson v Youden [1950] 1 KB 544.
Alternatively, if Ben
knew or believed the books to date from before 1800 he could be charged with
either:
(i) Doing an act
capable of encouraging or assisting the commission of an offence intending to
encourage or assist its commission contrary to s. 44 of the Serious
Crime Act 2007; or
(ii) Doing an act
capable of encouraging or assisting the commission of an offence believing that
the offence will be committed and that his act will encourage or assist its
commission contrary to s. 45 of the Serious Crime Act 2007.
The act in question
would be giving advice to Arthur he knew to be wrong. The fact that Arthur, in
destroying the books, might have acted without mens rea will not absolve Ben.
If the offence under the Ancient Book Act 2009 is construed as requiring fault
it will be suffi cient for the
prosecution to prove that Ben’s state of mind was such that, had he destroyed
the books, he would have acted with the degree of fault required for the full
offence; see s. 47(5)(a)(iii) of the 2007 Act. If the 2009 Act is a strict
liability offence, Ben can be convicted under the Serious Crime Act 2007,
provided he believed that the books dated from before 1800 or was reckless as
to whether or not they did.
Question 4
Gloria, Wood’s
eccentric aunt, aged 57, was invited to stay with Wood and his girlfriend Mary at
their property on the coast. It was agreed that Gloria would stay for three
weeks and would occupy ‘the lodge’ in the garden of the Wood’s house some 30 yards
away. Gloria also agreed to pay £40 to cover the electricity she would use in
the lodge. Everything went well for two weeks, with all three sharing meals at
the house. However, a change of mood then came over Gloria who decided that she
no longer wanted to have meals with Wood and Mary. Gloria spent more and more
time by herself at the lodge. After 20 days of the holiday Gloria, whose
physical condition had visibly deteriorated, announced that she refused to
leave the lodge and was going to stay there the rest of the winter. This so
enraged Wood and Mary that the next day they told her to leave immediately, which
she did. Six hours later, at 11 pm, Gloria rang their bell pleading to be let
in as she was cold and hungry and had nowhere else to go. Wood and Mary
refused, and during that night Gloria was taken to hospital suffering from
hypothermia. While in hospital, Gloria fell unconscious and was placed on a life
support machine. After five days she was correctly diagnosed by Dr Spock as
being in a persistent vegetative state with no hope of recovery. He accordingly
disconnected the machine. Discuss the criminal responsibility (if any) of Wood
and Mary.The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Answer plan
• Is there a
causative omission?
• Examine the bases
for liability for failing to act—statutory, contractual, and common law
• Distinguish R v
Instan and R v Stone & Dobinson
• Consider R v Miller
and R v Evans
• Consider killing by
gross negligence
• Can a duty of care
be established?
• Is the degree of
fault required made out on the facts?
Suggested answer
The first issue to be
resolved is whether or not Wood and Mary can be said to have caused the death
of Gloria. As there is no positive act by either of them that causes death, the
court would need to investigate whether or not liability can be based on the
failure of either or both of them to prevent Gloria’s death. The question as to
whether an omission, as opposed to an act, can actually cause a consequence is
a moot point. Traditionally, the criminal law has always drawn a clear
distinction between acts and omissions, being loath to punish the latter.
Other European countries—e.g., Greece,
France and Germany—do not exhibit the same reluctance, and there is dispute as
to whether the English approach is correct. See in particular the different
views of Professors A. Ashworth (1989) 105 LQR 424 and G. Williams (1991) 107
LQR 109. However, apart from the numerous statutes that impose a duty to act,
e.g., s. 170 of the Road Traffi c Act
1988, it appears that the common law will impose a duty to act only in very limited
circumstances. There can be no criminal liability imposed on Wood and Mary in
respect of their failing to care for Gloria unless the prosecution can
establish that they were under a positive legal duty to care for her. Such a
duty can be imposed by statute, but that is clearly not the case here.
Similarly a legal duty to act can arise from a contract between the parties. For
example in R v Pittwood (1902) 19 TLR 37, where the defendant, a railway gate operator,
was found guilty of manslaughter when a person was killed crossing a railway line
as a result of the defendant leaving the gate open when a train was coming. In
the present case it could be argued that there was a contractual relationship,
in that Gloria agreed to pay for her electricity and was in occupation of the
lodge, but it is hard to see how any positive duty to care for Gloria can be
implied—and in any event it would be argued that the contract was only for the
initial three-week period, and that it was a purely domestic arrangement not
intended to give rise to legally enforceable obligations.
In respect of Wood it
could be argued that he was under a common law duty to care for Gloria because
she was a relative. Where the relationship is that of parent and child the
common law has had little diffi culty in
identifying a positive legal duty of care so The elements of a crime: actus
reus and mens rea that failing to act can result in liability where it causes
harm; see R v Gibbins and Proctor (1918) 13 Cr App R 134. In R v Instan [1893]
1 QB 450, liability for manslaughter was imposed upon a niece who failed to
care for her aunt with whom she was living, having been given money by the aunt
to supply groceries. Liability in Instant was largely based on the existence of
a blood relationship between the parties. This would seem to suggest that, at
least in the case of Wood, there might be a common law duty to act. It is submitted
that the present case can be distinguished from Instan. In Instan the defend-ant
actually occupied the same house as the deceased, and had expressly undertaken
the task of purchasing food for her, which she subsequently failed to do,
knowing well that her aunt could not fend for herself. In the present case Gloria
decided for herself that she wanted to stay in the lodge alone, thus raising the
question of whether Wood was obliged to do anything more for her than he had
been doing during the fi rst two weeks of
her stay. Furthermore the evidence suggests that it was refusing to readmit
Gloria after she had been told to leave that led to her death—raising the question
of whether
Wood was under any
obligation to readmit Gloria. The much more promising argument for the
prosecution is that a positive legal duty to act at common law arose in respect
of both Wood and Mary because they had allowed a relationship of reliance to
develop between themselves and Gloria. The key authority here is R v Stone and
Dobinson [1977] QB 354. In that case the Court of Appeal upheld convictions for
killing by gross negligence on the basis that the defendants had admitted the
deceased to their house and had attempted to care for her. They then failed to
discharge their duty adequately and failed to summon any assistance in discharging
that duty. The court stressed that the duty to act arose not simply because of
a blood relationship between one of the defendants and the deceased, but
because of the reliance relationship. It could be argued that in allowing
Gloria to stay Wood and Mary allowed a relationship of reliance to develop—but
the present case can be distinguished from Stone and Dobinson on the grounds
that Wood and Mary placed a time limit on Gloria’s stay, and Gloria left of her
own volition. Thus the argument as to whether or not there is any liability for
failing to act is finely balanced. The prosecution could run an alternative
argument on the basis that when Gloria begs to be readmitted to the house Wood
and Mary are aware that their expulsion of Gloria has created a dangerous
situation. There is evidence that Gloria’s physical condition had visibly
deteriorated. Gloria was cold, hungry, and had nowhere to go. There was evidence
that Gloria was eccentric. Applying R v Miller [1983] 1 All ER 978, where the
House of
Lords upheld the
accused’s conviction for criminal damage where he had inadvertently started a
fi re and then, when he realized what he
had done, simply left the building without making any attempt to prevent the
fi re spreading or to call the fi re brigade, it could be argued that by
failing to offer Gloria shelter, Wood and Mary committed culpable omission that
caused Gloria’s death. For the Miller principle to apply, the prosecution would
have to show that the defendants were both aware that their expulsion of Gloria
had created a dangerous situation. On the facts this should not be too
difficult. The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Assuming that the
failure to care for Gloria, or the refusal to readmit her to the house, can
form the basis of liability, the prosecution will have to show that this
omission caused Gloria’s death. It is not necessary for the prosecution to
prove that the omission was the sole or main cause merely that it contributed
significantly to the victim’s death (R v Cheshire [1991] 3 All ER 670). The
accused could argue that the doctor’s turning off the life support system
constituted anovus actus interventions, breaking the chain of causation; but
this argument was rejected by the House of Lords in R v Malcherek; R v Steel
[1981] 2 All ER 422, where Lord Lane CJ stated that ‘the fact that the victim
has died, despite or because of medical treatment for the initial injury given
by careful and skilled medical practitioners, will not exonerate the original
assailant from responsibility for the death’. It is therefore clear that the
medical treatment, of itself, will not be held to have broken the chain of
causation in law. Wood and Mary could be charged with manslaughter on the basis
of killing by gross negligence, which, unlike unlawful act manslaughter, can be
based on an omission; see R v Lowe [1973] 1 All ER 805.
The key authority
regarding killing by gross negligence is the House of Lords’ ruling in R v
Adomako [1994] 3 All ER 79, where their Lordships held that an accused would be
guilty of manslaughter if the following four conditions were satisfi ed:
(i) The accused owed
a duty of care to the victim;
(ii) That duty was
broken;
(iii) The conduct of
the accused was grossly negligent;
(iv)That conduct
caused the victim’s death.
In some cases the
existence of a duty of care will be self-evident, for example doctor and
patient, parent and child etc. Notwithstanding the decision in R v Instan, it
should not be assumed that all familial relationships will give rise to a legal
duty of care, and in any event this would not assist as regards Mary. Significantly,
the Court of Appeal decision in R v Evans [2009] EWCA Crim 650, indicates that
a duty of care will be recognized by the courts in what might be referred to as
‘R v Miller’ situations—i.e., where the defendant has created a dangerous
situation and is aware, or ought reasonably to be aware, that this is the case.
Allowing Gloria’s physical condition to deteriorate and then not allowing her
back into the house might provide the evidential basis for this.
The trial judge in
the present case should direct that they can conclude that a duty of care
existed provided they find certain facts established—and the trial judge should
make clear to the jury what those key facts are. It is submitted that there is
sufficient evidence for the jury to conclude that a duty of care existed.
The breach of the
duty of care is evident in their not helping Gloria and not attempting to
obtain any alternative assistance for her—they did not even call the police to The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Commentary
Occasionally an exam
will contain a question that requires candidates to take a wider view of the
criminal law. This is such a question. Candidates cannot simply home in on a
specific area and cover it in detail. Candidates must try to think of instances
throughout the syllabus that can be used in your arguments to answer the
question. Avoid the common mistake of interpreting the question to read ‘Choose
one area of the criminal law where there are difficulties and write all about
them’! This question has been included as it enables candidates to think more
widely about the role of the criminal law within the legal system and society
as a whole. Providing a good answer requires the ability to take a broad view
of the syllabus—something candidates who revise topics in isolation are not
always able to do. Advise them of the problem. The issue of whether this breach
of the duty of care can be said to have caused the death of Gloria has already
been considered above.
The remaining live
issue, therefore, is that of gross negligence. Following the House of Lords’
decision in R v Adomako the jury will have to determine whether or not the accuser’s
conduct:
(a) departed from the
proper standard of care incumbent upon them;
(b) involved a risk
of death to the victim;
(c) was so grossly
negligent that it ought to be regarded as criminal.
As later cases such
as R v Mark and another [2004] All ER (D) 35 (Oct) indicate, actual foresight
of risk of death by the accused is not required. The test for mens rea is objective—does
the jury regard the act or omission leading to the breach of duty as being so
culpable that it should be labelled as ‘criminal’? Evidence that the defendants
knew they would cause harm by not acting is admissible to establish the
required fault, but is not essential. Similarly, evidence that Mary and Wood
had never thought about what might happen to Gloria could be admissible to show
that they should not be labeled as criminals, but such evidence would not
preclude a fi nding by the jury that
they had acted, or failed to act, in a manner that was grossly negligent.
Critically analyse
with reference to decided cases, the reasons why the development and application
of the criminal law is often unpredictable and inconsistent. The elements of a
crime: actus reus and mens rea
Answer plan
• Constant change—R v
R [1991]
• Lack of
code—Caldwell [1981], Morgan [1975]
• Logic v policy
• Role of House of
Lords—Clegg [1995]
Suggested answer
The development of
many areas of law follows a consistent and logical course. The basic
foundations, their concepts and application are accepted by the vast majority,
and only fine tuning or adjustments of these principles are required to meet
new situations. Unfortunately this cannot be said about criminal law, where the
debate about fundamental concepts—such as whether recklessness should be
interpreted subjectively or objectively; whether a mistake of fact relied upon
by a defendant should have to be one that a reasonable person would have made;
whether duress should be a defenses to a charge of murder—is still ongoing.
One of the problems
is that the criminal law is subject to constant change. It has to adapt to
cover new phenomena, such as stalking, drug abuse, and internet fraud and to
reflect society’s changing social and moral standards. As the House of Lords
stated in R v R [1991] 4 All ER 481, abolishing the husband’s marital rape
exemption, the common law is capable of evolving in the light of social, economic
and cultural developments. In that case the recognition that the status of
women had changed out of all recognition from the time (Hale’s Pleas of the
Crown 1736) when the husband’s marital rape exemption was initially recognized
was long overdue. Similarly, the criminal law once reflected the moral position
that it was a crime to take one’s own life. Failure in such an enterprise was
prosecuted as attempted suicide and could be punished. However, attitudes
softened and it was recognized that such a person needed help, not a criminal
trial; the law was consequently amended by the Suicide Act 1961. The 1960s saw similar
changes in respect of the law relating to homosexuality and abortion. Changes in
the law can also result from a shift in ideology on the part of an elected
government, or as a response to new threats to the safety and stability of
society—for example legislation to combat terrorism. There is no doubt that the
development and application of the criminal law would be more consistent and
predictable if the courts exhibited a more uniform approach to its development.
The problem is illustrated by two House of Lords’ decisions:
Metropolitan Police
Commissioner v Caldwell [1981] 1 All ER 961, where an objective approach to recklessness
was used, and DPP v Morgan [1975] 2 All ER 347, where a subjective approach to
mistake was applied. Why it was that liability for recklessness was imposed on
an objective basis, but where a defendant made a mistake of fact he The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea was entitled (subject to any
statutory provision to the contrary) to be judged on the facts as he honestly
believed them to be? Commentators may argue that two different areas of the
criminal law were being considered, criminal damage and rape (note that the law
has since been changed as regards rape by the Sexual Offences Act 2003), but
the inconsistency is still stark. At least in so far as recklessness is
concerned, the House of Lords has now embraced the notion of subjectivity again
in R v G [2003] 4 All ER 765, but the very fact that the legal definition of
such a basic concept can change so much in the space of 20 years is itself
startling.
The Law Commission
has long argued that the solution lies in codifying the law (see Law Com. No.
143) on the basis that: ‘the criminal law could then exhibit a uniform approach
to all crimes and defenses’.
All other major
European countries (France, Germany, and Spain) have a detailed criminal code,
with a uniform approach providing a starting point for interpreting the law.
The criminal law in England and Wales has developed in a piecemeal fashion,
with one offence’s development showing little consistency with another’s. So
often it is difficult to say what our law actually is, even before lawyers
start to debate how it should be applied, e.g., R v Savage; R v Parmenter
[1992] 1 AC 699, interpreting (after over 130 years of use) the provisions of
the Offences Against the Person Act 1861. A code could be expressed in clear
language with definitions of fundamental concepts such as intention and
recklessness, as suggested by the Law Commission’s Draft Criminal Code; although,
as the former chairman of the Law Commission Justice Henry Brooke stated ([1995]
Crim LR 911): ‘Nobody in their right mind would want to put the existing
criminal law into a codified form’.
Often the criminal
law follows a logical approach in its application; but as it does not exist in
a vacuum and is not simply the application of academic principles, policy considerations
sometimes have to prevail. As Lord Salmon stated in DPP v Majewski [1976] 2 All
ER 142, regarding the defence of intoxication, ‘the answer is that in strict logic
the view [intoxication is no defenses to crimes of basic intent] cannot be
justified. But this is the view that has been adopted by the common law which
is founded on common sense and experience rather than strict logic’. Policy
considerations are also behind s. 1(3) of the Criminal Attempts Act 1981,
whereby in the offence of attempt, the facts are to be as the accused believes
them to be. Thus an accused, objectively viewed, may appear not to be
committing a criminal act but because they believe they are, they can be guilty
of attempting to commit that criminal act, as in R v Shivpuri [1986] 2 All ER
334.
There is often no
means of predicting which approach will prevail. In Jaggard v Dickinson [1980]
3 All ER 716, the accused, who had been informed by her friend X that she could
break into X’s house to shelter, while drunk mistakenly broke into V’s house.
She was charged with criminal damage under s. 1(1) of the Criminal Damage Act 1971,
but argued that she had a lawful excuse under s. 5(2) of the Act as she
honestly believed that she had the owner’s consent. Although the prosecution
contended that this was a crime of basic intent and therefore drunkenness was
no defence (citing the The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
House of Lords’
decisions of Metropolitan Police Commissioner v Caldwell and DPP v Majewski in
support), the Court of Appeal quashed her conviction, giving priority to the
statutory provision of s. 5(2) of the 1971 Act. One important aspect of the
criminal law process in recent years, which has caused uncertainty, is the role
of the House of Lords in changing the criminal law. Clearly judges are there to
say what the law is, not what it should be; but Lord Simon in DPP for Northern
Ireland v Lynch [1975] 1 All ER 913 said: ‘I am all for recognizing that judges
do make law. And I am all for judges exercising their responsibilities boldly
at the proper time and place…where matters of social policy are not involved
which the collective wisdom of Parliament is better suited to resolve’. Thus in
R v R, the House of Lords changed the law of rape, by abolishing the husband’s
defence of marital rape immunity without waiting for Parliament to implement
the Law Commission’s recommendations. However, their Lordships took the opposite
view in R v Clegg [1995] 1 All ER 334, where they refused to follow the Law Commission’s
suggestion that a person who was entitled to use force in self-defense but who
used unreasonable force, thereby killing the victim, would be guilty of manslaughter,
not murder. Lord Lloyd stated:
I am not adverse to
judges developing law, or indeed making new law, when they can see their way
clearly, even where questions of social policy are involved. [A good example is
R v R.] But in the present case I am in no doubt that your Lordships should
abstain from law making. The reduction of what would otherwise be murder to
manslaughter in a particular class of case seems to me essentially a matter for
decision by the legislature. It is difficult to appreciate the essential
difference in issues in these two cases, despite Lord Lowry’s justifications in
R v Clegg that ‘R v R dealt with a specific act and not with a general
principle governing criminal liability’. Clearly there is a difference in
opinion amongst the Law Lords as to the correct application of these
principles. This is well illustrated by the House of Lords’ decision in R v
Gotts [1992] 1 All ER 832. The majority decision not to allow duress as a
defence to attempted murder was on the basis that duress was no defence to
murder. The minority view to the contrary revealed a different analysis. They
argued that duress is a general defence throughout the criminal law with the
exceptions of the offences of murder and treason. It is for Parliament, and not
the courts, to limit the ambit of a defence; and as attempted murder is a
different offence to murder, duress must therefore be available. It is
submitted that these are the main reasons why the development and application of
the criminal law is often uncertain and unpredictable. There are other factors,
such as whether an issue is a question of law for the judge or fact for the
jury, e.g., the meaning of ‘administer’ (R v Gillard (1988) 87 Cr App R 189);
the difficulty in ascertaining the ratio decided of many cases, e.g., R v Brown
[1993] 2 All ER 75 (consent); and the possible effect of the decisions of the
European Court of Human Rights. But it is the lack of a code and uniform
principles which are the main factors causing the inherent uncertainty.The elements
of a crime: actus reus and mens rea
Commentary
Liability for
omissions is a popular topic with examiners, either as an element of a problem question—typically
linked to killing by gross negligence to bring out the duty of care issues—or
as an essay topic in its own right. To deal comfortably with essay-style
questions on omissions it is necessary to have a good knowledge of the basic
cases. For degree level examinations, however, it is likely that some element
of analysis will be necessary. The extent to which this is the case will vary
according to the level at which the paper is set. Second and third year
undergraduates and CPE students would be expected to display more developed skills
of critical evaluation. Try to avoid simply describing the law—ensure that some
comment is provided on the examples given. There is not a great deal of
material on law reform in this area—the Law Commission has not explored it in
great detail, but it should not be difficult to identify some of the anomalies
that the case law throws up. For a flowchart on liability for failing to act,
Answer plan
• Basic rule on
liability for omissions
• Legal duty based on
statute
• Legal duty based on
contract
• Legal duty based on
office
• Common law duty to
act
• Where a duty ceases
to exist
• Possible reforms
Question 6
Critically assess the
grounds upon which liability for failing to act will be imposed in English criminal
law.
Suggested answer
Every offence in
criminal law requires proof of an actus reus on the part of the accused. In the
vast majority of cases statute or common law defi nes this actus reus in terms of a positive
act. Indeed, the expression actus reus literally translates as ‘guilty act’. A The
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea moment’s thought reveals, however,
that a defendant can commit an offence by failing to act, just as readily as he
can by positive action. If the parents of a newly born baby administer a lethal
dose of poison to the child no one would seriously suggest that there would be
a problem in establishing actus reus. Why should it be any different where the
defendants decide not to feed the child, with the result that the child dies of
starvation? The answer is that there is no difference in criminal law, but the
method by which liability is established may differ where it is based on an
omission as opposed to a positive act. The basic rule in English criminal law
is that there is no general positive duty to act to prevent the commission of
criminal offences or to limit the effect of harm caused by the actions of
others. This position reflects what is sometimes referred to as the individualistic
approach to liability. If D is at a swimming pool, and he sees P (a young child
with whom he has no connection) drowning in the deep end, why should D be
required to go to P’s aid? D has no special responsibility for P, and did not
cause the risk to arise. It is pure chance that D is in a position to help. Why
should fate be the basis for imposing a liability for failing to prevent P’s
death? Critics of the current position at common law argue for a ‘social
responsibility’ approach. This view proposes that liability should arise for
failing to attend those in peril partly because of the moral obligation to do
so, but also because it reflects a more complex social pact. A positive duty to
aid others would impose a responsibility but would also confer a corresponding
benefit. D might one day find himself compelled to help P, but the next day he
might be the benefi ciary of the duty on
P to aid D where D is in peril. At a macro level society benefits because less
harm is suffered by individuals. In reality English criminal law does impose
criminal liability for failing to act, but it does so on the basis of
exceptions. Thus D will not incur liability for failing to act unless the
prosecution can point to a positive legal duty to act.
The most obvious
source of such legal duties will be statute. Parliament creates liability for
failing to act in two ways. At a very simple level it creates offences of
omission. It is an offence for the owner of a vehicle to fail to display a
valid tax disc. It is an offence to fail to submit a tax return, or to provide
company accounts, etc. In these cases the omission itself is the crime. In many
cases they are offences of strict or absolute liability. Alternatively
Parliament may enact legislation that places a category of person under a duty
to act in a particular way. A failure to comply with this duty may result in
liability where the failure causes the commission of some prohibited
consequence. Perhaps the best known example of this is provided by the Children
and Young Persons Act 1933, which places parents and guardians under a legal
duty to care for children. Suppose that parents go out for the evening leaving
a four-year-old child alone. Whilst they are out he falls onto a fire and is
killed. It is likely that the court would find that there was a culpable
omission based on the breach of statutory duty, and liability could be imposed if
causation and fault are also established.
An alternative basis
for establishing a legal duty to act is where D is subject to a contractual
duty or holds an office that suggests the imposition of a duty. In the case of employees
the court will look at the express or implied terms of the contract to
determine The elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea the extent and nature
of the duties imposed on D. In R v Pittwood (1902) 19 TLR 37, a railway
crossing gatekeeper opened the gate to let a cart pass, but then went off to lunch,
forgetting to close the gate. A hay cart crossed the line and was hit by a
train. The defendant was convicted of manslaughter. He argued that the only
duty he owed was to his employers, with whom he had a contract. It was held,
however, that his contract imposed a wider duty upon him to users of the
crossing. Thus the duty arising under a contract inures to the benefit of those
who are not privy to the contract—i.e., the passengers on the train. In R v
Dytham [1979] 3 All ER 641, D was a police constable on duty. He witnessed V
being ejected from a nightclub and beaten up by a doorman. D did not intervene.
V died from his injuries. D was convicted of the common law offence of
misfeasance in public office and his appeal against conviction was dismissed.
The case begs the question—why was D not charged with causing the death of V by
his failure to intervene? The answer may be that in cases of failing to act,
proof of causation may be problematic. D obviously failed in his duty as a
police officer—but would his intervention have prevented V’s death? The mere
fact that there is an agreement between parties does not necessarily mean that
there will be a contractual duty to act. In R v Instan [1893] 1 QB 450, D was
given money by her aunt to buy groceries. D failed to care for her aunt who
subsequently died. It is unlikely that any contractual duty existed in this case,
as the agreement was a domestic one—hence there would have been no intention to
create legal relations.
Inevitably there are
situations where, despite the absence of any statutory or contractual duty to
act, it is felt that liability ought to be imposed. In such cases it falls to
the common law to perform its residual function of supplying the omission.
Judges ‘discover’ new common law duties to act because it is felt they ought to
exist. R v Instan is a case in point. For the last 12 days of her life the aunt
was suffering from gangrene in her leg and was unable to look after herself.
Only D knew this. D did not provide her aunt with food nor did she obtain
medical attention. This omission accelerated the aunt’s death. D’s conviction
for manslaughter was upheld, the court proceeding on the basis that a common
law duty was simply a moral duty so fundamental the courts had to enforce it.
As Lord Coleridge CJ observed, a legal common law duty is nothing else than the
enforcing by law of that which is a moral obligation without legal enforcement.
The problem with the
common law is that it is reactive—it only develops because cases come to the
courts on appeal. A narrow reading of R v Instan suggests that a common law
duty is owed to one’s blood relatives, but clearly the scope should be wider than
that. The court in R v Gibbins and Proctor (1918) 13 Cr App R 134, accepted that
a duty could be imposed upon a common law wife to care for her partner’s child because,
although the child was not hers, she had assumed a duty towards the child by choosing
to live with the child’s father and accept housekeeping money to buy food for them
all. The problem with such rulings is that the limits of liability are left vague—what
if D had lived with the child’s father only on weekends? Imposing liability for
omissions where D undertakes to care for P and P becomes reliant on D may even
be counter-productive. In R v Stone and Dobinson [1977] QB 354, the defendants
were convicted of the manslaughter of Stone’s sister Fanny because they the
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens reatook her in but failed to care for
her adequately. With hindsight they might have been advised not to help her in
the fi rst place. The law therefore
sends mixed messages. One ought to care for others, but one should not start to
do so unless one is able to discharge that duty properly.
The common law duty
to act was developed further by the important House of Lords’ decision in R v
Miller [1983] 1 All ER 978. D, who was squatting in an empty house, fell asleep
whilst smoking a cigarette. Whilst he was asleep the cigarette set fire to the mattress.
D woke, realized the mattress was on fi
re, but took no steps to douse the fire. The house was damaged in the
ensuing blaze. He was obviously not under a statutory duty to put the fire out,
nor was he under a contractual duty to do so. At the time the common law duties
to act were based on duties owed to blood relatives, or arising from reliance.
The House of Lords had little choice but to ‘discover’ a new legal duty at
common law. Such a duty arises where D accidentally causes harm, realizes that
he has done so, and it lies within his power to take steps, either himself or by
calling for the assistance to prevent or minimize the harm. The omission itself
is not, of course, the offence. For criminal damage it must be shown that the
omission caused the harm, and that D had the requisite mens rea at the time of
the actus reus. The doctrine has since been applied to killing by gross
negligence in R v Evans (Gemma) [2009] EWCA 650, where it was held that
awareness of having caused a dangerous situation could of itself give rise to
the duty of care (effectively the duty to act) that forms the basis of the offence.
Whilst the ruling in R v Miller is socially desirable—there is great social utility
in D being required to limit the effect of his careless actions—there are many
uncertainties. What is it that D is required to do once he realizes he has
caused harm? Is the test objective or subjective? Must he act as the reasonable
person would have done, or does he simply have to do his best? The latter would
certainly accord with the general trend towards subjectivity in criminal law.
Even where a positive
legal duty to act can be identified, uncertainties may arise as to whether D
has been or can be absolved from that duty. In R v Smith [1979] Crim LR 251,
D’s wife was seriously ill. She asked D not to seek help. Her condition
worsened and she eventually asked D to get help, which he did, but it was too
late to save her. D was charged with manslaughter and the trial judge directed
the jury that D was under a duty by virtue of being the victim’s husband, but
he could be released from that duty if she so indicated and she were of sound
mind at the time. This places the husband in a difficult legal position. At
what point must he ignore his wife’s wishes and obtain medical help? Some
clarification is provided by the House of Lords’ decision in Airedale NHS Trust
v Bland [1993] AC 789, where it was held that doctors were under a duty to
treat a patient where it was in the patient’s best interests to do so. Where,
however, all hope of the patient recovering had disappeared, the duty to nourish
and maintain the patient would also cease. To date the Law Commission has done
little more than suggest a codification of the common law position as outlined
above. It is submitted that a more radical approach would be to adopt the
French model of creating a general statutory duty of ‘easy rescue’. Essentially
there would be liability for failing to prevent harm where such prevention the
elements of a crime: actus reus and mens rea would not be too onerous or difficult
for D to achieve. The accident that led to the death of Princess Diana in the
Paris underpass illustrates the point. French photographers were charged with
manslaughter based on their failure to help because they allegedly photographed
the crash scene when they could have been offering aid to the injured. Such a
prosecution would not have been possible under English law.
Further reading Amirthalingam,
K., ‘Caldwell Recklessness is Dead, Long Live Mens Rea’s Fecklessness’ [2004]
MLR 491.Ashworth, A., ‘Interpreting Criminal Statutes’ [1991] LQR 419.Ashworth,
A. and Blake, M., ‘The Presumption of Innocence in English Criminal Law’ [1996]
Crim LR 306.Kaveny, C.M., ‘Inferring Intention from Foresight’ (2004) LQR 120.Keating,
H., ‘Reckless Children?’ [2007] Crim LR 546.Norrie, A., ‘Oblique Intent and
Legal Politics’ [1989] Crim LR 793.Pedain, A., ‘Intention and the Terrorist
Example’ [2003] Crim LR 549.Smith, J.C., ‘R v Woollin’ [1998] Crim LR 890.
No comments:
Post a Comment